Distributive Princi­ p les of Criminal Law 5 are exactly the ­people over which the criminal justice system wants to take control. Punishing insane offenders would also send a useful general deterrent message to other (noninsane) potential offenders, demonstrating how serious the system is about punishing violators. A desert princi­ple, in contrast, would insist on exculpating offenders whose insanity renders them blameless.1 Another example illustrates that while deterrence and incapacitation princi­ ples may agree on the insanity defense issue, they commonly disagree with one another. Where an attempt fails by chance—­the intended victim bends down to tie his shoe at the moment before the assailant’s bullet is about to strike his head—­ t he incapacitation princi­ p le would punish the failed attempt the same as a successful attempt ­ b ecause the assailant is equally dangerous in both cases, while a deterrence princi­ple would want to punish the attempt less seriously than the completed offense so as to maintain a continuing threat of additional punishment to deter a follow-up attempt. If the failed attacker is already fully liable, why ­ w ouldn’t he try again? If desert ­were the distributive princi­ple in the attempted murder case, it is unclear what the result would be ­ u nder deontological desert: moral phi­los­o­ phers are divided over ­ w hether the resulting death should increase the actor’s punishment where his conduct and culpability are identical. On the other hand, ­ under what one might call “empirical desert,” the result is clear: ordi- nary ­people essentially universally agree that the resulting harm should increase punishment, that murder should be punished more seriously than attempted murder. ­ There are hundreds of issues like the insanity defense and the significance of resulting harm about which alternative princi­ples differ in their distribu- tion of criminal liability and punishment. ­ Every jurisdiction in the United States, through constitutional provision, statutory provision, state sentencing commission policy, or appellate court opinion, gives some indication of the princi­ple or princi­ples that should be used in constructing, interpreting, or applying its criminal liability and sen- tencing rules.2 States are ­free to adopt any distributive princi­ple or combina- tion of princi­ p les that they choose ­ t here is no federal constitutional limitation on their choice. As Justice Anthony Kennedy wrote in an Eighth Amendment case before the U.S. Supreme Court, “­there are a variety of legitimate peno- logical schemes based on the theories of retribution, deterrence, incapacita- tion, and rehabilitation, and the Eighth Amendment does not mandate the adoption of any one such scheme.”3 And, as Map 1A makes clear, states have exercised this right to choose in a wide variety of ways. Desert as a Distributive Princi­ple Thirty states, designated with light shading on the map—­ A labama, Alaska, Arizona, Arkansas, California, Colorado, Connecticut, Hawaii, Idaho, Kentucky, Louisiana, Mary­ l and, Mas­ s c hu­ s etts, Mississippi, New Jersey, New Mexico, New
Previous Page Next Page